Here’s a guide to some of the logical notation Lewis uses in his article.
Thor gave a speech and then Thor thanked Odin for helping to defeat Loki.
T
or perhaps T[Thor]
. The advantage of second abbreviation is then we can also talk about T[Freyja]
, which would be the same sentence, but with all occurrences of Thor
replaced with Freyja
, thusly:Freyja gave a speech and then Freyja thanked Odin for helping to defeat Loki.
T[Thor, Odin, Loki]
. Then T[Freyja, Frigg, Baldr]
would be:Freyja gave a speech and then Freyja thanked Frigg for helping to defeat Baldr.
T[Odin, Freyja, Frigg]
would be:Odin gave a speech and then Odin thanked Freyja for helping to defeat Frigg.
Sometimes instead of names, we use symbols like t1, t2, t3
. When we want to talk about these three symbols as a combined triple, we can write it as t1, …, tn
, and we call that an “n-tuple” (in this case, n
= 3).
We sometimes write the n-tuple t1, …, tn
as t (with an overbar) or as boldface t.
Thus if t1, t2, t3
= (Thor, Odin, Loki) and v1, v2, v3
= (Odin, Freyja, Frigg), then T[t]
is the first of our sentences above, and T[v]
is the fourth.
∀x (if x a Norse god, then x is famous).
∃x (x a Norse god, and x is famous).
to mean “There is at least one (possibly more) Norse god, and he/she/they are famous.”
∃x1 ∃x2 ∃x3 (x1, x2, and x3 are Norse gods, and T[x1, x2, x3])
This sentence doesn’t reqire that x1, x2, and x3
be distinct people; thus one way for that sentence to be true would be if x1, x2, x3
= (Thor, Loki, Loki) and Thor was thanking Loki for helping to defeat Loki.
These symbols ∀ and ∃ are called “quantifiers.” The first one looks like it does because it has a meaning similar to the English “all” and “any”; the second has a meaning similar to the English “there exists”.
There is a unique triple of things (x1, x2, x3) such that T[x1, x2, x3]
There is a unique triple of things x such that T[x]
∃1 (x1, x2, x3) such that T[x1, x2, x3]
∃1x such that T[x]
E!
, that has a different meaning.) Or you can see it written like this:∃x ∀y (T[y] ↔︎ x = y).
p ↔︎ q
means that “If p is the case, then q is the case; and also if q is the case, then p is the case.” Or as philosophers abbreviate it, p iff q
. Iff
stands for for “if and only if”. So expanding that last sentence, it’s equivalent to:∃x ∀y (x = y → T[y] and T[y] → x = y).
∃x ∀y (T[x] and T[y] → x = y).
the
. So if there is a unique Norse god who defeated Loki, then we can talk about “the Norse god who defeated Loki”, or, more formally, as:the x: x is a Norse god who defeated Loki
If Thor defeated Loki and nobody else also defeated Loki, then this description will designate Thor. If nobody defeated Loki, or multiple people did, then that would be called an “improper description.” Philosophers disagree about what happens with them. Russell talked about the description “the present king of France.” He was writing long after France stopped having a king. Russell’s view was that sentences like “The present king of France is bald” should be false, since there is no present king of France. Other philosophers argued that this sentence is neither true nor false.
the
, philosophers sometimes write definite descriptions using an upside-down Greek letter iota, so it looks like this:℩x: x is a Norse god who defeated Loki
t = ℩x T[x]
What he means by that is that t1, …, tn
are identical to the unique x1, …, xn
such that T[x1, …, xn
].