From: jim Date: Sun, 15 Feb 2015 14:27:26 +0000 (-0500) Subject: refinements X-Git-Url: http://lambda.jimpryor.net/git/gitweb.cgi?p=lambda.git;a=commitdiff_plain;h=34b8b8d3486290342c79905d16a93fa06475f71d refinements --- diff --git a/topics/week3_combinatory_logic.mdwn b/topics/week3_combinatory_logic.mdwn index df568dc3..d24e6c11 100644 --- a/topics/week3_combinatory_logic.mdwn +++ b/topics/week3_combinatory_logic.mdwn @@ -3,9 +3,9 @@ Combinators and Combinatory Logic Combinatory logic is of interest here in part because it provides a useful computational system that is equivalent to the Lambda Calculus, -but different from it. In addition, Combinatory Logic has a number of +but different from it. In addition, Combinatory Logic has a number of applications in natural language semantics. Exploring Combinatory -Logic will involve defining a different notion of reduction from the +Logic will involve defining a notion of reduction different from the one we have been using for the Lambda Calculus. This will provide us with a second parallel example when we're thinking through topics such as evaluation strategies and recursion. @@ -32,23 +32,11 @@ over the first two arguments. > **C** is defined to be: `\f x y. f y x`. (So `C f` is a function like `f` except it expects its first two (curried) arguments in flipped order.) -> **W** is defined to be: `\f x . f x x`. (So `W f` accepts one argument and gives it to `f` twice. What is the meaning of `W multiply`?) - -> **ω** (that is, lower-case omega) is defined to be: `\x. x x`. Sometimes this combinator is called **M**. - - -S, K, I, B also known ---> +> **ω** (that is, lower-case omega) is defined to be: `\x. x x`. Sometimes this combinator is called **M**. It and `W` both duplicate arguments, just in different ways. It's possible to build a logical system equally powerful as the Lambda Calculus @@ -74,40 +62,38 @@ natural language denotation is a combinator. For instance, Szabolcsi 1987 argues that reflexive pronouns are argument duplicators. -

-everyone   hit           himself
-S/(S!NP)   (S!NP)/NP     (S!NP)!((S!NP)/NP)
-\f∀x[fx]   \y\z[HIT y z] \h\u[huu]
-           ---------------------------------
-                  S!NP     \u[HIT u u]
---------------------------------------------
-                  S        ∀x[HIT x x]
-
+ everyone hit himself + S/(S!NP) (S!NP)/NP (S!NP)!((S!NP)/NP) + \f∀x[fx] \y\z[HIT y z] \h\u[huu] + --------------------------------- here "hit" is an argument to "himself" + S!NP \u[HIT u u] + -------------------------------------------- here "hit himself" is an argument to "everyone" + S ∀x[HIT x x] Notice that the semantic value of *himself* is exactly `W`. The reflexive -pronoun in direct object position combines with the transitive verb. The -result is an intransitive verb phrase that takes a subject argument, duplicates +pronoun in direct object position combines with the transitive verb "hit". The +result is an intransitive verb phrase "hit himself" that takes a subject argument `u`, duplicates that argument, and feeds the two copies to the transitive verb meaning. Note that `W <~~> S(CI)`: -
S(CI) ≡
-S((\fxy.fyx)(\x.x)) ~~>
-S(\xy.(\x.x)yx) ~~>
-S(\xy.yx) ≡
-(\fgx.fx(gx))(\xy.yx) ~~>
-\gx.(\xy.yx)x(gx) ~~>
-\gx.(gx)x ≡
-W
+ S(CI) ≡ + S ((\f x y. f y x) (\x x)) ~~> + S (\x y. (\x x) y x) ~~> + S (\x y. y x) ≡ + (\f g x. f x (g x)) (\x y. y x) ~~> + \g x. (\x y. y x) x (g x) ~~> + \g x. (g x) x ≡ + W ###A different set of reduction rules### -Instead of defining combinators in terms of antecedently understood lambda terms, we want to consider the view that takes the combinators as primitive, and understands them in terms of *what they do*. If we have the `I` combinator followed by any expression X, -`I` will take that expression as its argument and return that same expression as the result. In pictures, +Instead of defining combinators in terms of antecedently understood lambda terms, we want to consider the view that takes the combinators as primitive, and understands them in terms of *what they do*. If we have the `I` combinator followed by any expression `X`, +`I` will take that expression as its argument and return that same expression as the result. Diagrammatically: IX ~~> X -Thinking of this as a reduction rule, we can perform the following computation +Thinking of this as a reduction rule, we can perform the following computation: II(IX) ~~> I(IX) ~~> IX ~~> X @@ -118,7 +104,7 @@ The reduction rule for `K` is also straightforward: That is, `K` throws away its second argument. The reduction rule for `S` can be constructed by examining the defining lambda term: -
S ≡ \fgx.fx(gx)
+ S ≡ \f g x. f x (g x) `S` takes three arguments, duplicates the third argument, and feeds one copy to the first argument and the second copy to the second argument. So: @@ -133,26 +119,27 @@ certain crafty combination of `S`s and `K`s: SKKX ~~> KX(KX) ~~> X -So the combinator `SKK` is equivalent to the combinator `I`. (Really, it could be `SKX` for any `X`.) +So the combinator `SKK` is equivalent to the combinator `I`. (Really, it could be `SKY` for any `Y`.) These reduction rule have the same status with respect to Combinatory -Logic as beta reduction and eta reduction, etc., have with respect to +Logic as beta-reduction and eta-reduction have with respect to the Lambda Calculus: they are purely syntactic rules for transforming one sequence of symbols (e.g., a redex) into another (a reduced form). It's worth noting that the reduction rules for Combinatory Logic are considerably more simple than, say, beta reduction. Also, since -there are no variables in Combiantory Logic, there is no need to worry +there are no variables in Combinatory Logic, there is no need to worry about variables colliding when we substitute. Combinatory Logic is what you have when you choose a set of combinators and regulate their behavior with a set of reduction rules. As we said, the most common system uses `S`, `K`, and `I` as defined here. ###The equivalence of the untyped Lambda Calculus and Combinatory Logic### -We've claimed that Combinatory Logic is equivalent to the Lambda Calculus. If +We've claimed that Combinatory Logic is "equivalent to" the Lambda Calculus. If that's so, then `S`, `K`, and `I` must be enough to accomplish any computational task imaginable. Actually, `S` and `K` must suffice, since we've just seen that we can simulate `I` using only `S` and `K`. In order to get an intuition about what it -takes to be Turing complete, recall our discussion of the Lambda Calculus in +takes to be Turing Complete, +recall our discussion of the Lambda Calculus in terms of a text editor. A text editor has the power to transform any arbitrary text into any other arbitrary text. The way it does this is by deleting, copying, and reordering characters. We've @@ -162,8 +149,8 @@ enough to define arbitrary functions. We've already established that the behavior of combinatory terms can be perfectly mimicked by lambda terms: just replace each combinator with its -equivalent lambda term, i.e., replace `I` with `\x.x`, replace `K` with `\xy.x`, -and replace `S` with `\fgx.fx(gx)`. So the behavior of any combination of +equivalent lambda term, i.e., replace `I` with `\x. x`, replace `K` with `\x y. x`, +and replace `S` with `\f g x. f x (g x)`. So the behavior of any combination of combinators in Combinatory Logic can be exactly reproduced by a lambda term. How about the other direction? Here is a method for converting an arbitrary @@ -173,10 +160,10 @@ says about the nature of binding and computation, it is possible to hear an echo of computing with continuations in this conversion strategy (though you wouldn't be able to hear these echos until we've covered a considerable portion of the rest of the course). In addition, there is a direct linguistic -appliction of this mapping in chapter 17 of Barker and Shan 2014, where it is -used to establish a correpsondence between two natural language grammars, one +application of this mapping in chapter 17 of Barker and Shan 2014, where it is +used to establish a correspondence between two natural language grammars, one of which is based on lambda-like abstraction, the other of which is based on -Combinatory Logic like manipulations. +Combinatory Logic-like manipulations. Assume that for any lambda term T, [T] is the equivalent Combinatory Logic term. Then we can define the [.] mapping as follows: @@ -199,24 +186,24 @@ The third rule should be obvious. The fourth rule should also be fairly self-evident: since what a lambda term such as `\x. y` does it throw away its first argument and return `y`, that's exactly what the Combinatory Logic translation should do. And indeed, `K y` is a function that throws away its argument and returns `y`. -The fifth rule deals with an abstract whose body is an application: the `S` combinator takes its next argument (which will fill the role of the original variable a) and copies it, feeding one copy to the translation of \a.M, and the other copy to the translation of \a.N. This ensures that any free occurrences of a inside M or N will end up taking on the appropriate value. +The fifth rule deals with an abstract whose body is an application: the `S` combinator takes its next argument (which will fill the role of the original variable a) and copies it, feeding one copy to the translation of `\a. M`, and the other copy to the translation of `\a. N`. This ensures that any free occurrences of a inside `M` or `N` will end up taking on the appropriate value. -Finally, the last rule says that if the body of an abstract is itself an abstract, translate the inner abstract first, and then do the outermost. (Since the translation of [\b.M] will not have any lambdas in it, we can be sure that we won't end up applying rule 6 again in an infinite loop.) +Finally, the last rule says that if the body of an abstract is itself an abstract, translate the inner abstract first, and then do the outermost. (Since the translation of `[\b. M]` will have eliminated any inner lambdas, we can be sure that we won't end up applying rule 6 again in an infinite loop.) Persuade yourself that if the original lambda term contains no free variables --- i.e., is a combinator --- then the translation will consist only of `S`, `K`, and `I` (plus parentheses). -(Fussy note: this translation algorithm builds expressions that combine lambdas with combinators. For instance, the translation of our boolean false `\x. \y. y` is `[\x [\y. y]] = [\x. I] = KI`. In the intermediate stage, we have `\x. I`, which mixes primitive combinators in the body of a lambda abstract. It's possible to avoid this if you want to, but it takes some careful thought. See, e.g., Barendregt 1984, page 156.) +(Fussy note: this translation algorithm builds intermediate expressions that combine lambdas with primitive combinators. For instance, the translation of our boolean `false` (`\x y. y`) is `[\x [\y. y]] = [\x. I] = KI`. In the intermediate stage, we have `\x. I`, which has a combinator in the body of a lambda abstract. It's possible to avoid this if you want to, but it takes some careful thought. See, e.g., Barendregt 1984, page 156.) Various, slightly differing translation schemes from Combinatory Logic to the Lambda Calculus are also possible. These generate different metatheoretical -correspondences between the two calculii. Consult Hindley and Seldin for +correspondences between the two calculi. Consult Hindley and Seldin for details. Also, note that the combinatorial proof theory needs to be strengthened with axioms beyond anything we've here described in order to make [M] convertible with [N] whenever the original lambda-terms M and N are convertible. But then, we've been a bit cavalier about giving the full set of -reduction rules for the Lambda Calculus in a similar way. +reduction rules for the Lambda Calculus in a similar way. For instance, one issue we mentioned in the notes on [[Reduction Strategies|week3_reduction_strategies]] is whether reduction rules (in either the Lambda Calculus or Combinatory Logic) apply to embedded expressions. Often, we do want that to happen, but @@ -228,21 +215,27 @@ Let's check that the translation of the `false` boolean behaves as expected by f Throws away the first argument, returns the second argument---yep, it works. -Here's a more elaborate example of the translation. The goal is to establish that combinators can reverse order, so we use the **T** combinator, where T ≡ \x y. y x: +Here's a more elaborate example of the translation. Let's say we want to establish that combinators can reverse order, so we use the **T** combinator (`\x y. y x`): - [\x y. y x] = [\x [\y. y x]] = [\x. S [\y. y] [\y. x]] = [\x.(SI)(Kx)] = S[\x.SI][\x.Kx] = S(K(SI))(S[\x.K][\x.x]) = S(K(SI))(S(KK)I) + [\x y. y x] = + [\x [\y. y x]] = + [\x. S [\y. y] [\y. x]] = + [\x. (SI) (K x)] = + S [\x. SI] [\x. K x] = + S (K(SI)) (S [\x. K] [\x. x]) = + S (K(SI)) (S(KK)I) We can test this translation by seeing if it behaves like the original lambda term does. The orginal lambda term lifts its first argument (think of it as reversing the order of its two arguments): - S(K(SI))(S(KK)I) X Y ~~> - (K(SI))X ((S(KK)I) X) Y ~~> - SI ((KK)X (IX)) Y ~~> - SI (KX) Y ~~> - IY (KXY) ~~> - Y X + S (K(SI)) (S(KK)I) X Y ~~> + (K(SI))X ((S(KK)I) X) Y ~~> + SI ((KK)X (IX)) Y ~~> + SI (K X) Y ~~> + IY (KXY) ~~> + Y X -Voilà: the combinator takes any X and Y as arguments, and returns Y applied to X. +Voilà: the combinator takes any X and Y as arguments, and returns Y applied to X. One very nice property of Combinatory Logic is that there is no need to worry about alphabetic variance, or variable collision---since there are no (bound) variables, there is no possibility of accidental variable capture, @@ -252,42 +245,42 @@ an appreciation of that intricacy is to write a program that performs lambda red Back to linguistic applications: one consequence of the equivalence between the Lambda Calculus and Combinatory Logic is that anything that can be done by binding variables can just as well be done with combinators. -This has given rise to a style of semantic analysis called Variable Free Semantics (in addition to +This has given rise to a style of semantic analysis called Variable-Free Semantics (in addition to Szabolcsi's papers, see, for instance, Pauline Jacobson's 1999 *Linguistics and Philosophy* paper, "Towards a variable-free Semantics"). Somewhat ironically, reading strings of combinators is so difficult that most practitioners of variable-free semantics -express their meanings using the Lambda Calculus rather than Combinatory Logic; perhaps they should call their -enterprise Free Variable Free Semantics. +express their meanings using the Lambda Calculus rather than Combinatory Logic. Perhaps they should call their +enterprise *Free Variable*-Free Semantics. -A philosophical connection: Quine went through a phase in which he developed a variable free logic. +A philosophical connection: Quine went through a phase in which he developed a variable-free logic. > Quine, Willard. 1960. "Variables explained away" Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society. Volume 104: 343--347. Also in W. V. Quine. 1960. Selected Logical Papers. Random House: New York. 227--235. The reason this was important to Quine is similar to the worry that using -non-referring expressions such as Santa Claus might commit one to believing in +non-referring expressions such as `Santa Claus` might commit one to believing in non-existent things. Quine's slogan was that "to be is to be the value of a variable." What this was supposed to mean is that if and only if an object could serve as the value of some variable, we are committed to recognizing the -existence of that object in our ontology. Obviously, if there ARE no +existence of that object in our ontology. Obviously, if there *are* no variables, this slogan has to be rethought. Quine did not appear to appreciate that Shoenfinkel had already invented Combinatory Logic, though he later wrote an introduction to Shoenfinkel's key paper reprinted in Jean van Heijenoort (ed) 1967 From Frege to Goedel, a source book in mathematical logic, 1879--1931. -Cresswell has also developed a variable-free approach of some philosophical and linguistic interest -in two books in the 1990's. +Cresswell also developed a variable-free approach of some philosophical and linguistic interest +in two books in the 1990s. A final linguistic application: Steedman's Combinatory Categorial Grammar, where the "Combinatory" is from Combinatory Logic (see especially his 2012 book, Taking Scope). Steedman attempts to build -a syntax/semantics interface using a small number of combinators, including `T` ≡ `\x y. y x`, `B` ≡ `\f x y. f (x y)`, +a syntax/semantics interface using a small number of combinators, including `T` (`\x y. y x`), `B` (`\f g x. f (g x)`), and our friend `S`. Steedman used Smullyan's fanciful bird -names for the combinators, Thrush, Bluebird, and Starling. +names for these combinators: Thrush, Bluebird, and Starling. Many of these combinatory logics, in particular, the SKI system, -are Turing complete. In other words: every computation we know how to describe can be represented in a logical system consisting of only a single primitive operation! - +are Turing Complete. In other words: every computation we know how to describe can be represented in a logical system consisting of only primitive combinators, even some systems with only a *single* primitive combinator. + ###A connection between Combinatory Logic and Sentential Logic### @@ -297,10 +290,9 @@ The combinators `K` and `S` correspond to two well-known axioms of sentential lo AS: (A ⊃ (B ⊃ C)) ⊃ ((A ⊃ B) ⊃ (A ⊃ C)) When these two axiom schemas are combined with the rule of modus ponens (from `A` and `A ⊃ B`, conclude `B`), the resulting proof system -is complete for the implicational fragment of intuitionistic logic. -(To get a complete proof system for *classical* sentential logic, you -need only add one more axiom schema, constraining the behavior of a new connective "not".) -The way we'll favor for viewing the relationship between these axioms +is complete for the "implicational fragment" of intuitionistic logic. (That is, the part of intuitionistic logic you get when `⊃` is your only connective. To get a complete proof system for *classical* sentential logic, you +need only add one more axiom schema, constraining the behavior of a new connective `¬`.) +The way we'll favor viewing the relationship between these axioms and the `S` and `K` combinators is that the axioms correspond to *type schemas* for the combinators. This will become more clear once we have a theory of types in view.