X-Git-Url: http://lambda.jimpryor.net/git/gitweb.cgi?p=lambda.git;a=blobdiff_plain;f=week8.mdwn;h=cd99b421c6627abdeb555b5de5d1b13290c38f70;hp=e99e223ab91f6bf1d4bbd350355f0f9ecaeed97c;hb=ac1241bd46013ce4d552868fae863d1921420eb6;hpb=adaf5a4a914b56ca7be6c3fce6da8269e1ed23ca diff --git a/week8.mdwn b/week8.mdwn index e99e223a..cd99b421 100644 --- a/week8.mdwn +++ b/week8.mdwn @@ -11,24 +11,28 @@ positions. The system does not make use of assignment functions or variables. We'll see that from the point of view of our discussion of monads, Jacobson's system is essentially a reader monad in which the assignment function threaded through the computation is limited to at -most one assignment. +most one assignment. More specifically, Jacobson's geach combinator +*g* is exactly our `lift` operator, and her binding combinator *z* is +exactly our `bind` with the arguments reversed! Jacobson's system contains two main combinators, *g* and *z*. She calls *g* the Geach rule, and *z* effects binding. (There is a third -combinator, *l*, which we'll make use of to adjust function/argument -order to better match English word order; N.B., though, that -Jacobson's name for this combinator is "lift", but it is different -from the monadic lift discussed in some detail below.) Here is a -typical computation (based closely on email from Simon Charlow, with -beta reduction as performed by the on-line evaluator): +combinator which following Curry and Steedman, I'll call *T*, which +we'll make use of to adjust function/argument order to better match +English word order; N.B., though, that Jacobson's name for this +combinator is "lift", but it is different from the monadic lift +discussed in some detail below.) Here is a typical computation (based +closely on email from Simon Charlow, with beta reduction as performed +by the on-line evaluator):
 ; Analysis of "Everyone_i thinks he_i left"
 let g = \f g x. f (g x) in
 let z = \f g x. f (g x) x in
-let everyone = \P. FORALL x (P x) in
 let he = \x. x in
-everyone ((z thinks) (g left he))
+let everyone = \P. FORALL x (P x) in
+
+everyone (z thinks (g left he))
 
 ~~>  FORALL x (thinks (left x) x)
 
@@ -44,8 +48,8 @@ Second, *g* plays the role of transmitting a binding dependency for an embedded constituent to a containing constituent. If the sentence had been *Everyone_i thinks Bill said he_i left*, there would be an occurrence of *g* in the most deeply embedded clause (*he left*), and -another occurrence of (a variant of) *g* in the next most deeply -embedded clause (*Bill said he left*). +another occurrence of *g* in the next most deeply +embedded constituent (*said he left*), and so on (see below). Third, binding is accomplished by applying *z* not to the element that will (in some pre-theoretic sense) bind the pronoun, here, *everyone*, @@ -136,14 +140,14 @@ the parallel with the reader monad even more by writing a `shift` operator that used `unit` to produce a monadic result, if we wanted to. The monad version of *Everyone_i thinks he_i left*, then (remembering -that `he = fun x -> x`, and that `l a f = f a`) is +that `he = fun x -> x`, and letting `t a f = f a`) is
 everyone (z thinks (g left he))
 
 ~~> forall w (thinks (left w) w)
 
-everyone (z thinks (g (l bill) (g said (g left he))))
+everyone (z thinks (g (t bill) (g said (g left he))))
 
 ~~> forall w (thinks (said (left w) bill) w)
 
@@ -154,3 +158,96 @@ Jacobson's variable-free semantics is essentially a reader monad. One of Jacobson's main points survives: restricting the reader monad to a single-value environment eliminates the need for variable names. + +Binding more than one variable at a time +---------------------------------------- + +It requires some cleverness to use the link monad to bind more than +one variable at a time. Whereas in the standard reader monad a single +environment can record any number of variable assignments, because +Jacobson's monad only tracks a single dependency, binding more than +one pronoun requires layering the monad. (Jacobson provides some +special combinators, but we can make do with the ingredients already +defined.) + +Let's take the following sentence as our target, with the obvious +binding relationships: + +
+    John believes Mary said he thinks she's cute.
+     |             |         |         |
+     |             |---------|---------|
+     |                       |
+     |-----------------------|
+
+ +It will be convenient to +have a counterpart to the lift operation that combines a monadic +functor with a non-monadic argument: + +
+    let g f v = ap (unit f) v;;
+    let g2 u a = ap u (unit a);;
+
+ +As a first step, we'll bind "she" by "Mary": + +
+believes (z said (g2 (g thinks (g cute she)) she) mary) john
+
+~~> believes (said (thinks (cute mary) he) mary) john
+
+ +As usual, there is a trail of *g*'s leading from the pronoun up to the +*z*. Next, we build a trail from the other pronoun ("he") to its +binder ("John"). + +
+believes
+  said 
+    thinks (cute she) he
+    Mary
+  John
+
+believes
+  z said
+    (g2 ((g thinks) (g cute she))) he
+    Mary
+  John
+
+z believes
+  (g2 (g (z said)
+         (g (g2 ((g thinks) (g cute she))) 
+            he))
+      Mary)
+  John
+
+ +In the first interation, we build a chain of *g*'s and *g2*'s from the +pronoun to be bound ("she") out to the level of the first argument of +*said*. + +In the second iteration, we treat the entire structure as ordinary +functions and arguments, without "seeing" the monadic region. Once +again, we build a chain of *g*'s and *g2*'s from the currently +targeted pronoun ("he") out to the level of the first argument of +*believes*. (The new *g*'s and *g2*'s are the three leftmost). + +
+z believes (g2 (g (z said) (g (g2 ((g thinks) (g cute she))) he)) mary) john
+
+~~> believes (said (thinks (cute mary) john) mary) john
+
+ +Obviously, we can repeat this strategy for any configuration of pronouns +and binders. + +This binding strategy is strongly reminiscent of the translation from +the lambda calculus into Combinatory Logic that we studied earlier +(see the lecture notes for week 2). Recall that bound pronouns ended +up translating to I, the identity combinator, just like Jacobson's +identity functions for pronouns; abstracts (\a.M) whose body M did not +contain any occurrences of the pronoun to be bound translated as KM, +just like our unit, K; and abstracts of the form (\a.MN) translated to +S[\aM][\aN], just like our ap rule. +