X-Git-Url: http://lambda.jimpryor.net/git/gitweb.cgi?p=lambda.git;a=blobdiff_plain;f=week1.mdwn;h=1bc2309e1e9c79eea7118b9f6e72045a90b3317d;hp=2c686583929b8e65d537b04ada523f7909c45813;hb=c86596d41ed6ca32fff882b468eade84bc13fb07;hpb=74149f64a2c684075745513abc97730f034a65d4 diff --git a/week1.mdwn b/week1.mdwn index 2c686583..1bc2309e 100644 --- a/week1.mdwn +++ b/week1.mdwn @@ -57,7 +57,7 @@ We'll tend to write (λa M) as just `(\a M)`, so we don't hav Application: (M N) -Some *authors* reserve the term "term" for just variables and abstracts. We won't participate in that convention; we'll probably just say "term" and "expression" indiscriminately for expressions of any of these three forms. +Some authors reserve the term "term" for just variables and abstracts. We'll probably just say "term" and "expression" indiscriminately for expressions of any of these three forms. Examples of expressions: @@ -74,7 +74,7 @@ The lambda calculus has an associated proof theory. For now, we can regard the proof theory as having just one rule, called the rule of **beta-reduction** or "beta-contraction". Suppose you have some expression of the form: - ((\a M) N) + ((\ a M) N) that is, an application of an abstract to some other expression. This compound form is called a **redex**, meaning it's a "beta-reducible expression." `(\a M)` is called the **head** of the redex; `N` is called the **argument**, and `M` is called the **body**. @@ -285,18 +285,16 @@ It's possible to enhance the lambda calculus so that functions do get identified It's often said that dynamic systems are distinguished because they are the ones in which **order matters**. However, there are many ways in which order can matter. If we have a trivalent boolean system, for example---easily had in a purely functional calculus---we might choose to give a truth-table like this for "and": -

-true and true   = true
-true and true   = true
-true and *      = *
-true and false  = false
-* and true      = *
-* and *         = *
-* and false     = *
-false and true  = false
-false and *     = false
-false and false = false
-
+ true and true = true + true and true = true + true and * = * + true and false = false + * and true = * + * and * = * + * and false = * + false and true = false + false and * = false + false and false = false And then we'd notice that `* and false` has a different intepretation than `false and *`. (The same phenomenon is already present with the material conditional in bivalent logics; but seeing that a non-symmetric semantics for `and` is available even for functional languages is instructive.) @@ -603,7 +601,6 @@ Here's how it looks to say the same thing in various of these languages. It's easy to be lulled into thinking this is a kind of imperative construction. *But it's not!* It's really just a shorthand for the compound "let"-expressions we've already been looking at, taking the maximum syntactically permissible scope. (Compare the "dot" convention in the lambda calculus, discussed above.) - 9. Some shorthand OCaml permits you to abbreviate: @@ -674,9 +671,8 @@ Here's how it looks to say the same thing in various of these languages. and there's no more mutation going on there than there is in: -
-	∀x. (F x or ∀x (not (F x)))
-	
+
∀x. (F x or ∀x (not (F x)))
+	
When a previously-bound variable is rebound in the way we see here, that's called **shadowing**: the outer binding is shadowed during the scope of the inner binding.