X-Git-Url: http://lambda.jimpryor.net/git/gitweb.cgi?p=lambda.git;a=blobdiff_plain;f=topics%2F_week5_system_F.mdwn;h=242ada430c4430e6076b668dbb6c4d819a6ad6a8;hp=4517509b28236e8cab4d3c4123b4e03c5be348c5;hb=3286774dd5086d93efc40df3c846f26b3f5b39ef;hpb=293b63f453994f8c3c458ca264ef0fb04b79e1fb diff --git a/topics/_week5_system_F.mdwn b/topics/_week5_system_F.mdwn index 4517509b..242ada43 100644 --- a/topics/_week5_system_F.mdwn +++ b/topics/_week5_system_F.mdwn @@ -9,23 +9,6 @@ simply-typed lambda calculus as a way of expressing natural language meaning. So we will need to get more sophisticated about types. The next step in that journey will be to consider System F. -In the simply-typed lambda calculus, we write types like σ --> τ. This looks like logical implication. We'll take -that resemblance seriously when we discuss the Curry-Howard -correspondence. In the meantime, note that types respect modus -ponens: - -
-Expression    Type      Implication
------------------------------------
-fn            α -> β    α ⊃ β
-arg           α         α
-------        ------    --------
-(fn arg)      β         β
-
- -The implication in the right-hand column is modus ponens, of course. - System F was discovered by Girard (the same guy who invented Linear Logic), but it was independently proposed around the same time by Reynolds, who called his version the *polymorphic lambda calculus*. @@ -122,9 +105,9 @@ however. Here is one way: let fst = λx:N. λy:N. x in let snd = λx:N. λy:N. y in let pair = λx:N. λy:N. λz:N->N->N. z x y in - let suc = λn:N. Λα. λs:α->α. λz:α. s (n [α] s z) in - let shift = λp:Pair. pair (suc (p fst)) (p fst) in - let pre = λn:N. n [Pair] shift (pair zero zero) snd in + let succ = λn:N. Λα. λs:α->α. λz:α. s (n [α] s z) in + let shift = λp:Pair. pair (succ (p fst)) (p fst) in + let pred = λn:N. n [Pair] shift (pair zero zero) snd in pre (suc (suc (suc zero))); @@ -138,24 +121,25 @@ reserved words in Pierce's system.] Exercise: convince yourself that `zero` has type `N`. The key to the extra expressive power provided by System F is evident -in the typing imposed by the definition of `pre`. The variable `n` is -typed as a Church number, i.e., as `∀α.(α->α)->α->α`. The type -application `n [Pair]` instantiates `n` in a way that allows it to -manipulate ordered pairs: `n [Pair]: (Pair->Pair)->Pair->Pair`. In -other words, the instantiation turns a Church number into a +in the typing imposed by the definition of `pred`. The variable `n` +is typed as a Church number, i.e., as `N ≡ ∀α.(α->α)->α->α`. +The type application `n [Pair]` instantiates `n` in a way that allows +it to manipulate ordered pairs: `n [Pair]: (Pair->Pair)->Pair->Pair`. +In other words, the instantiation turns a Church number into a certain pair-manipulating function, which is the heart of the strategy for -this version of predecessor. - -Could we try to build a system for doing Church arithmetic in which -the type for numbers always manipulated ordered pairs? The problem is -that the ordered pairs we need here are pairs of numbers. If we tried -to replace the type for Church numbers with a concrete (simple) type, -we would have to replace each `X` with the type for Pairs, `(N -> N -> -N) -> N`. But then we'd have to replace each of these `N`'s with the -type for Church numbers, `(α -> α) -> α -> α`. And then we'd have to -replace each of these `α`'s with... ad infinitum. If we had to choose -a concrete type built entirely from explicit base types, we'd be -unable to proceed. +this version of computing the predecessor function. + +Could we try to accommodate the needs of the predecessor function by +building a system for doing Church arithmetic in which the type for +numbers always manipulated ordered pairs? The problem is that the +ordered pairs we need here are pairs of numbers. If we tried to +replace the type for Church numbers with a concrete (simple) type, we +would have to replace each `N` with the type for Pairs, `(N -> N -> N) +-> N`. But then we'd have to replace each of these `N`'s with the +type for Church numbers, which we're imagining is `(Pair -> Pair) -> +Pair -> Pair`. And then we'd have to replace each of these `Pairs`'s +with... ad infinitum. If we had to choose a concrete type built +entirely from explicit base types, we'd be unable to proceed. [See Benjamin C. Pierce. 2002. *Types and Programming Languages*, MIT Press, chapter 23.] @@ -171,9 +155,7 @@ it is even possible to give a type for ω in System F. In order to see how this works, we'll apply ω to the identity function. -ω id == - - (λx:(∀α.α->α). x [∀α.α->α] x) (Λα.λx:α.x) +ω id ≡ (λx:(∀α.α->α). x [∀α.α->α] x) (Λα.λx:α.x) Since the type of the identity function is `∀α.α->α`, it's the right type to serve as the argument to ω. The definition of @@ -196,8 +178,8 @@ form in a finite number of steps. Not only does a fixed-point combinator remain out of reach, we can't even construct an infinite loop. This means that although we found a type for ω, there is no general type for Ω ≡ ω -ω. Furthermore, it turns out that no Turing complete system can -be strongly normalizing, from which it follows that System F is not +ω. In fact, it turns out that no Turing complete system can be +strongly normalizing, from which it follows that System F is not Turing complete. @@ -210,10 +192,11 @@ The classic case study motivating polymorphism in natural language comes from coordination. (The locus classicus is Partee and Rooth 1983.) - Ann left and Bill left. - Ann left and slept. - Ann and Bill left. - Ann read and reviewed the book. + Type of the argument of "and": + Ann left and Bill left. t + Ann left and slept. e->t + Ann and Bill left. (e->t)-t (i.e, generalize quantifiers) + Ann read and reviewed the book. e->e->t In English (likewise, many other languages), *and* can coordinate clauses, verb phrases, determiner phrases, transitive verbs, and many @@ -221,7 +204,9 @@ other phrase types. In a garden-variety simply-typed grammar, each kind of conjunct has a different semantic type, and so we would need an independent rule for each one. Yet there is a strong intuition that the contribution of *and* remains constant across all of these -uses. Can we capture this using polymorphic types? +uses. + +Can we capture this using polymorphic types? Ann, Bill e left, slept e -> t @@ -230,38 +215,41 @@ uses. Can we capture this using polymorphic types? With these basic types, we want to say something like this: and:t->t->t = λl:t. λr:t. l r false - and = Λα.Λβ.λl:α->β.λr:α->β.λx:α. and [β] (l x) (r x) - -The idea is that the basic *and* conjoins expressions of type `t`, and -when *and* conjoins functional types, it builds a function that -distributes its argument across the two conjuncts and conjoins the two -results. So `Ann left and slept` will evaluate to `(\x.and(left -x)(slept x)) ann`. Following the terminology of Partee and Rooth, the -strategy of defining the coordination of expressions with complex -types in terms of the coordination of expressions with less complex -types is known as Generalized Coordination. - -But the definitions just given are not well-formed expressions in -System F. There are three problems. The first is that we have two -definitions of the same word. The intention is for one of the -definitions to be operative when the type of its arguments is type -`t`, but we have no way of conditioning evaluation on the *type* of an -argument. The second is that for the polymorphic definition, the term -*and* occurs inside of the definition. System F does not have -recursion. - -The third problem is more subtle. The defintion as given takes two -types as parameters: the type of the first argument expected by each -conjunct, and the type of the result of applying each conjunct to an -argument of that type. We would like to instantiate the recursive use -of *and* in the definition by using the result type. But fully -instantiating the definition as given requires type application to a -pair of types, not to just a single type. We want to somehow -guarantee that β will always itself be a complex type. - -So conjunction and disjunction provide a compelling motivation for -polymorphism in natural language, but we don't yet have the ability to -build the polymorphism into a formal system. + gen_and = Λα.Λβ.λf:(β->t).λl:α->β.λr:α->β.λx:α. f (l x) (r x) + +The idea is that the basic *and* (the one defined in the first line) +conjoins expressions of type `t`. But when *and* conjoins functional +types (the definition in the second line), it builds a function that +distributes its argument across the two conjuncts and then applies the +appropriate lower-order instance of *and*. + + and (Ann left) (Bill left) + gen_and [e] [t] and left slept + gen_and [e] [e->t] (gen_and [e] [t] and) read reviewed + +Following the terminology of Partee and Rooth, this strategy of +defining the coordination of expressions with complex types in terms +of the coordination of expressions with less complex types is known as +Generalized Coordination, which is why we call the polymorphic part of +the definition `gen_and`. + +In the first line, the basic *and* is ready to conjoin two truth +values. In the second line, the polymorphic definition of `gen_and` +makes explicit exactly how the meaning of *and* when it coordinates +verb phrases depends on the meaning of the basic truth connective. +Likewise, when *and* coordinates transitive verbs of type `e->e->t`, +the generalized *and* depends on the `e->t` version constructed for +dealing with coordinated verb phrases. + +On the one hand, this definition accurately expresses the way in which +the meaning of the conjunction of more complex types relates to the +meaning of the conjunction of simpler types. On the other hand, it's +awkward to have to explicitly supply an expression each time that +builds up the meaning of the *and* that coordinates the expressions of +the simpler types. We'd like to have that automatically handled by +the polymorphic definition; but that would require writing code that +behaved differently depending on the types of its type arguments, +which goes beyond the expressive power of System F. And in fact, discussions of generalized coordination in the linguistics literature are almost always left as a meta-level @@ -270,6 +258,10 @@ Hendriks' 1992:74 dissertation, generalized coordination is implemented as a method for generating a suitable set of translation rules, which are in turn expressed in a simply-typed grammar. +There is some work using System F to express generalizations about +natural language: Ponvert, Elias. 2005. Polymorphism in English Logical +Grammar. In *Lambda Calculus Type Theory and Natural Language*: 47--60. + Not incidentally, we're not aware of any programming language that makes generalized coordination available, despite is naturalness and ubiquity in natural language. That is, coordination in programming