X-Git-Url: http://lambda.jimpryor.net/git/gitweb.cgi?p=lambda.git;a=blobdiff_plain;f=topics%2F_week5_system_F.mdwn;h=242ada430c4430e6076b668dbb6c4d819a6ad6a8;hp=2c37ae3467e0f01203fb4ebb5dcdc203a3067ea5;hb=3286774dd5086d93efc40df3c846f26b3f5b39ef;hpb=cbf0c724914abae08e00292bdcbd3dea1f9460cd diff --git a/topics/_week5_system_F.mdwn b/topics/_week5_system_F.mdwn index 2c37ae34..242ada43 100644 --- a/topics/_week5_system_F.mdwn +++ b/topics/_week5_system_F.mdwn @@ -1,21 +1,13 @@ -# System F and recursive types +[[!toc levels=2]] -In the simply-typed lambda calculus, we write types like σ --> τ. This looks like logical implication. We'll take -that resemblance seriously when we discuss the Curry-Howard -correspondence. In the meantime, note that types respect modus -ponens: +# System F: the polymorphic lambda calculus -
-Expression    Type      Implication
------------------------------------
-fn            α -> β    α ⊃ β
-arg           α         α
-------        ------    --------
-(fn arg)      β         β
-
- -The implication in the right-hand column is modus ponens, of course. +The simply-typed lambda calculus is beautifully simple, but it can't +even express the predecessor function, let alone full recursion. And +we'll see shortly that there is good reason to be unsatisfied with the +simply-typed lambda calculus as a way of expressing natural language +meaning. So we will need to get more sophisticated about types. The +next step in that journey will be to consider System F. System F was discovered by Girard (the same guy who invented Linear Logic), but it was independently proposed around the same time by @@ -24,77 +16,266 @@ Reynolds, who called his version the *polymorphic lambda calculus*. continuations.) System F enhances the simply-typed lambda calculus with abstraction -over types. In order to state System F, we'll need to adopt the -notational convention that "x:α" represents a -expression whose type is α. - -Then System F can be specified as follows (choosing notation that will -match up with usage in O'Caml, whose type system is based on System F): - - System F: - types τ ::= c | 'a | τ1 -> τ2 | ∀'a. τ - expressions e ::= x | λx:τ. e | e1 e2 | Λ'a. e | e [τ] - -In the definition of the types, "`c`" is a type constant (e.g., `e` or -`t`). "`'a`" is a type variable (the tick mark just indicates that -the variable ranges over types rather than values). "`τ1 -> τ2`" is -the type of a function from expressions of type `τ1` to expressions of -type `τ2`. And "`∀'a. τ`" is called a universal type, since it -universally quantifies over the type variable `'a`. - -In the definition of the expressions, we have variables "`x`". -Abstracts "`λx:τ. e`" are similar to abstracts in the simply-typed lambda +over types. Normal lambda abstraction abstracts (binds) an expression +(a term); type abstraction abstracts (binds) a type. + +In order to state System F, we'll need to adopt the +notational convention (which will last throughout the rest of the +course) that "x:α" represents an expression `x` +whose type is α. + +Then System F can be specified as follows: + + System F: + --------- + types τ ::= c | α | τ1 -> τ2 | ∀α.τ + expressions e ::= x | λx:τ.e | e1 e2 | Λα.e | e [τ] + +In the definition of the types, "`c`" is a type constant. Type +constants play the role in System F that base types play in the +simply-typed lambda calculus. So in a lingusitics context, type +constants might include `e` and `t`. "α" is a type variable. In +various discussions, type variables are distinguished by using letters +from the greek alphabet (α, β, etc.), as we do here, or by +using capital roman letters (X, Y, etc.), or by adding a tick mark +(`'a`, `'b`, etc.), as in OCaml. "`τ1 -> τ2`" is the type of a +function from expressions of type `τ1` to expressions of type `τ2`. +And "`∀α.τ`" is called a universal type, since it universally +quantifies over the type variable `α`. You can expect that in +`∀α.τ`, the type `τ` will usually have at least one free occurrence of +`α` somewhere inside of it. + +In the definition of the expressions, we have variables "`x`" as usual. +Abstracts "`λx:τ.e`" are similar to abstracts in the simply-typed lambda calculus, except that they have their shrug variable annotated with a type. Applications "`e1 e2`" are just like in the simply-typed lambda calculus. + In addition to variables, abstracts, and applications, we have two -additional ways of forming expressions: "`Λ'a. e`" is a type -abstraction, and "`e [τ]`" is a type application. The idea is that -Λ is a capital λ. Just like -the lower-case λ, Λ binds -variables in its body; unlike λ, -Λ binds type variables. So in the expression +additional ways of forming expressions: "`Λα.e`" is called a *type +abstraction*, and "`e [τ]`" is called a *type application*. The idea +is that Λ is a capital λ: just +like the lower-case λ, Λ binds +variables in its body, except that unlike λ, +Λ binds type variables instead of expression +variables. So in the expression + +Λ Î± (λ x:α. x) -Λ 'a (λ x:'a . x) +the Λ binds the type variable `α` that occurs in +the λ abstract. -the Λ binds the type variable `'a` that occurs in -the λ abstract. This expression is a polymorphic -version of the identity function. It says that this one general -identity function can be adapted for use with expressions of any -type. In order to get it ready to apply to, say, a variable of type -boolean, just do this: +This expression is a polymorphic version of the identity function. It +defines one general identity function that can be adapted for use with +expressions of any type. In order to get it ready to apply this +identity function to, say, a variable of type boolean, just do this: -(Λ 'a (λ x:'a . x)) [t] +(Λ Î± (λ x:α. x)) [t] -The type application (where `t` is a type constant for Boolean truth -values) specifies the value of the type variable `α`, which is -the type of the variable bound in the `λ` expression. Not -surprisingly, the type of this type application is a function from -Booleans to Booleans: +This type application (where `t` is a type constant for Boolean truth +values) specifies the value of the type variable `α`. Not +surprisingly, the type of the expression that results from this type +application is a function from Booleans to Booleans: -((Λ 'a (λ x:'a . x)) [t]): (b -> b) +((Λα (λ x:α . x)) [t]): (b->b) Likewise, if we had instantiated the type variable as an entity (base type `e`), the resulting identity function would have been a function of type `e -> e`: -((Λ 'a (λ x:'a . x)) [e]): (e -> e) +((Λα (λ x:α. x)) [e]): (e->e) -Clearly, for any choice of a type `'a`, the identity function can be -instantiated as a function from expresions of type `'a` to expressions -of type `'a`. In general, then, the type of the unapplied +Clearly, for any choice of a type `α`, the identity function can be +instantiated as a function from expresions of type `α` to expressions +of type `α`. In general, then, the type of the uninstantiated (polymorphic) identity function is -(Λ 'a (λ x:'a . x)): (\forall 'a . 'a -> 'a) - - - - -## - +(Λα (λx:α . x)): (∀α. α->α) + +Pred in System F +---------------- + +We saw that the predecessor function couldn't be expressed in the +simply-typed lambda calculus. It *can* be expressed in System F, +however. Here is one way: + + let N = ∀α.(α->α)->α->α in + let Pair = (N->N->N)->N in + + let zero = Λα. λs:α->α. λz:α. z in + let fst = λx:N. λy:N. x in + let snd = λx:N. λy:N. y in + let pair = λx:N. λy:N. λz:N->N->N. z x y in + let succ = λn:N. Λα. λs:α->α. λz:α. s (n [α] s z) in + let shift = λp:Pair. pair (succ (p fst)) (p fst) in + let pred = λn:N. n [Pair] shift (pair zero zero) snd in + + pre (suc (suc (suc zero))); + +[If you want to run this code in +[[Benjamin Pierce's type-checker and evaluator for +System F|http://www.cis.upenn.edu/~bcpierce/tapl/index.html]], the +relevant evaluator is called "fullpoly", and you'll need to +truncate the names of "suc(c)" and "pre(d)", since those are +reserved words in Pierce's system.] + +Exercise: convince yourself that `zero` has type `N`. + +The key to the extra expressive power provided by System F is evident +in the typing imposed by the definition of `pred`. The variable `n` +is typed as a Church number, i.e., as `N ≡ ∀α.(α->α)->α->α`. +The type application `n [Pair]` instantiates `n` in a way that allows +it to manipulate ordered pairs: `n [Pair]: (Pair->Pair)->Pair->Pair`. +In other words, the instantiation turns a Church number into a certain +pair-manipulating function, which is the heart of the strategy for +this version of computing the predecessor function. + +Could we try to accommodate the needs of the predecessor function by +building a system for doing Church arithmetic in which the type for +numbers always manipulated ordered pairs? The problem is that the +ordered pairs we need here are pairs of numbers. If we tried to +replace the type for Church numbers with a concrete (simple) type, we +would have to replace each `N` with the type for Pairs, `(N -> N -> N) +-> N`. But then we'd have to replace each of these `N`'s with the +type for Church numbers, which we're imagining is `(Pair -> Pair) -> +Pair -> Pair`. And then we'd have to replace each of these `Pairs`'s +with... ad infinitum. If we had to choose a concrete type built +entirely from explicit base types, we'd be unable to proceed. + +[See Benjamin C. Pierce. 2002. *Types and Programming Languages*, MIT +Press, chapter 23.] + +Typing ω +-------------- +In fact, unlike in the simply-typed lambda calculus, +it is even possible to give a type for ω in System F. + +ω = λx:(∀α.α->α). x [∀α.α->α] x + +In order to see how this works, we'll apply ω to the identity +function. + +ω id ≡ (λx:(∀α.α->α). x [∀α.α->α] x) (Λα.λx:α.x) + +Since the type of the identity function is `∀α.α->α`, it's the +right type to serve as the argument to ω. The definition of +ω instantiates the identity function by binding the type +variable `α` to the universal type `∀α.α->α`. Instantiating the +identity function in this way results in an identity function whose +type is (in some sense, only accidentally) the same as the original +fully polymorphic identity function. + +So in System F, unlike in the simply-typed lambda calculus, it *is* +possible for a function to apply to itself! + +Does this mean that we can implement recursion in System F? Not at +all. In fact, despite its differences with the simply-typed lambda +calculus, one important property that System F shares with the +simply-typed lambda calculus is that they are both strongly +normalizing: *every* expression in either system reduces to a normal +form in a finite number of steps. + +Not only does a fixed-point combinator remain out of reach, we can't +even construct an infinite loop. This means that although we found a +type for ω, there is no general type for Ω ≡ ω +ω. In fact, it turns out that no Turing complete system can be +strongly normalizing, from which it follows that System F is not +Turing complete. + + +## Polymorphism in natural language + +Is the simply-typed lambda calclus enough for analyzing natural +language, or do we need polymorphic types? Or something even more expressive? + +The classic case study motivating polymorphism in natural language +comes from coordination. (The locus classicus is Partee and Rooth +1983.) + + Type of the argument of "and": + Ann left and Bill left. t + Ann left and slept. e->t + Ann and Bill left. (e->t)-t (i.e, generalize quantifiers) + Ann read and reviewed the book. e->e->t + +In English (likewise, many other languages), *and* can coordinate +clauses, verb phrases, determiner phrases, transitive verbs, and many +other phrase types. In a garden-variety simply-typed grammar, each +kind of conjunct has a different semantic type, and so we would need +an independent rule for each one. Yet there is a strong intuition +that the contribution of *and* remains constant across all of these +uses. + +Can we capture this using polymorphic types? + + Ann, Bill e + left, slept e -> t + read, reviewed e -> e -> t + +With these basic types, we want to say something like this: + + and:t->t->t = λl:t. λr:t. l r false + gen_and = Λα.Λβ.λf:(β->t).λl:α->β.λr:α->β.λx:α. f (l x) (r x) + +The idea is that the basic *and* (the one defined in the first line) +conjoins expressions of type `t`. But when *and* conjoins functional +types (the definition in the second line), it builds a function that +distributes its argument across the two conjuncts and then applies the +appropriate lower-order instance of *and*. + + and (Ann left) (Bill left) + gen_and [e] [t] and left slept + gen_and [e] [e->t] (gen_and [e] [t] and) read reviewed + +Following the terminology of Partee and Rooth, this strategy of +defining the coordination of expressions with complex types in terms +of the coordination of expressions with less complex types is known as +Generalized Coordination, which is why we call the polymorphic part of +the definition `gen_and`. + +In the first line, the basic *and* is ready to conjoin two truth +values. In the second line, the polymorphic definition of `gen_and` +makes explicit exactly how the meaning of *and* when it coordinates +verb phrases depends on the meaning of the basic truth connective. +Likewise, when *and* coordinates transitive verbs of type `e->e->t`, +the generalized *and* depends on the `e->t` version constructed for +dealing with coordinated verb phrases. + +On the one hand, this definition accurately expresses the way in which +the meaning of the conjunction of more complex types relates to the +meaning of the conjunction of simpler types. On the other hand, it's +awkward to have to explicitly supply an expression each time that +builds up the meaning of the *and* that coordinates the expressions of +the simpler types. We'd like to have that automatically handled by +the polymorphic definition; but that would require writing code that +behaved differently depending on the types of its type arguments, +which goes beyond the expressive power of System F. + +And in fact, discussions of generalized coordination in the +linguistics literature are almost always left as a meta-level +generalizations over a basic simply-typed grammar. For instance, in +Hendriks' 1992:74 dissertation, generalized coordination is +implemented as a method for generating a suitable set of translation +rules, which are in turn expressed in a simply-typed grammar. + +There is some work using System F to express generalizations about +natural language: Ponvert, Elias. 2005. Polymorphism in English Logical +Grammar. In *Lambda Calculus Type Theory and Natural Language*: 47--60. + +Not incidentally, we're not aware of any programming language that +makes generalized coordination available, despite is naturalness and +ubiquity in natural language. That is, coordination in programming +languages is always at the sentential level. You might be able to +evaluate `(delete file1) and (delete file2)`, but never `delete (file1 +and file2)`. + +We'll return to thinking about generalized coordination as we get +deeper into types. There will be an analysis in term of continuations +that will be particularly satisfying. + + +#Types in OCaml -Types in OCaml --------------- OCaml has type inference: the system can often infer what the type of an expression must be, based on the type of other known expressions.