X-Git-Url: http://lambda.jimpryor.net/git/gitweb.cgi?p=lambda.git;a=blobdiff_plain;f=advanced_topics%2Fmonads_in_category_theory.mdwn;h=173160e51c310018c87b43984820f3ffcffd176e;hp=07977f29b4328b4f46a2d3e5efda8f227bba1d11;hb=446376aee15c6fbc9d71383d1c7654fd02ebb8f6;hpb=9e80b25daf1427ebcde2715e35de10dc1a2dfa78 diff --git a/advanced_topics/monads_in_category_theory.mdwn b/advanced_topics/monads_in_category_theory.mdwn index 07977f29..173160e5 100644 --- a/advanced_topics/monads_in_category_theory.mdwn +++ b/advanced_topics/monads_in_category_theory.mdwn @@ -1,6 +1,3 @@ -**Don't try to read this yet!!! Many substantial edits are still in process. -Will be ready soon.** - Caveats ------- I really don't know much category theory. Just enough to put this @@ -8,11 +5,16 @@ together. Also, this really is "put together." I haven't yet found an authoritative source (that's accessible to a category theory beginner like myself) that discusses the correspondence between the category-theoretic and functional programming uses of these notions in enough detail to be sure that -none of the pieces here is misguided. In particular, it wasn't completely -obvious how to map the polymorphism on the programming theory side into the -category theory. And I'm bothered by the fact that our `<=<` operation is only -partly defined on our domain of natural transformations. But this does seem to -me to be the reasonable way to put the pieces together. We very much welcome +none of the pieces here is mistaken. +In particular, it wasn't completely obvious how to map the polymorphism on the +programming theory side into the category theory. The way I accomplished this +may be more complex than it needs to be. +Also I'm bothered by the fact that our `<=<` operation is only partly defined +on our domain of natural transformations. +There are three additional points below that I wonder whether may be too +cavalier. +But all considered, this does seem to +me to be a reasonable way to put the pieces together. We very much welcome feedback from anyone who understands these issues better, and will make corrections. @@ -33,8 +35,8 @@ Some examples of monoids are: * finite strings of an alphabet `A`, with being concatenation and `z` being the empty string * all functions X→X over a set `X`, with being composition and `z` being the identity function over `X` -* the natural numbers with being plus and `z` being `0` (in particular, this is a **commutative monoid**). If we use the integers, or the naturals mod n, instead of the naturals, then every element will have an inverse and so we have not merely a monoid but a **group**.) -* if we let be multiplication and `z` be `1`, we get different monoids over the same sets as in the previous item. +* the natural numbers with being plus and `z` being 0 (in particular, this is a **commutative monoid**). If we use the integers, or the naturals mod n, instead of the naturals, then every element will have an inverse and so we have not merely a monoid but a **group**. +* if we let be multiplication and `z` be 1, we get different monoids over the same sets as in the previous item. Categories ---------- @@ -51,28 +53,28 @@ To have a category, the elements and morphisms have to satisfy some constraints: (ii) composition of morphisms has to be associative - (iii) every element E of the category has to have an identity - morphism 1E, which is such that for every morphism f:C1→C2: + (iii) every element X of the category has to have an identity + morphism 1X, which is such that for every morphism f:C1→C2: 1C2 ∘ f = f = f ∘ 1C1 -These parallel the constraints for monoids. Note that there can be multiple distinct morphisms between an element `E` and itself; they need not all be identity morphisms. Indeed from (iii) it follows that each element can have only a single identity morphism. +These parallel the constraints for monoids. Note that there can be multiple distinct morphisms between an element `X` and itself; they need not all be identity morphisms. Indeed from (iii) it follows that each element can have only a single identity morphism. -A good intuitive picture of a category is as a generalized directed graph, where the category elements are the graph's nodes, and there can be multiple directed edges between a given pair of nodes, and nodes can also have multiple directed edges to themselves. (Every node must have at least one such, which is that node's identity morphism.) +A good intuitive picture of a category is as a generalized directed graph, where the category elements are the graph's nodes, and there can be multiple directed edges between a given pair of nodes, and nodes can also have multiple directed edges to themselves. Morphisms correspond to directed paths of length ≥ 0 in the graph. Some examples of categories are: * Categories whose elements are sets and whose morphisms are functions between those sets. Here the source and target of a function are its domain and range, so distinct functions sharing a domain and range (e.g., `sin` and `cos`) are distinct morphisms between the same source and target elements. The identity morphism for any element/set is just the identity function for that set. -* any monoid (S,⋆,z) generates a category with a single element `x`; this `x` need not have any relation to `S`. The members of `S` play the role of *morphisms* of this category, rather than its elements. All of these morphisms are understood to map `x` to itself. The result of composing the morphism consisting of `s1` with the morphism `s2` is the morphism `s3`, where s3=s1⋆s2. The identity morphism for the (single) category element `x` is the monoid's identity `z`. +* any monoid (S,⋆,z) generates a category with a single element `Q`; this `Q` need not have any relation to `S`. The members of `S` play the role of *morphisms* of this category, rather than its elements. All of these morphisms are understood to map `Q` to itself. The result of composing the morphism consisting of `s1` with the morphism `s2` is the morphism `s3`, where s3=s1⋆s2. The identity morphism for the (single) category element `Q` is the monoid's identity `z`. -* a **preorder** is a structure (S, ≤) consisting of a reflexive, transitive, binary relation on a set `S`. It need not be connected (that is, there may be members `x`,`y` of `S` such that neither x≤y nor y≤x). It need not be anti-symmetric (that is, there may be members `s1`,`s2` of `S` such that s1≤s2 and s2≤s1 but `s1` and `s2` are not identical). Some examples: +* a **preorder** is a structure (S, ≤) consisting of a reflexive, transitive, binary relation on a set `S`. It need not be connected (that is, there may be members `s1`,`s2` of `S` such that neither s1 ≤ s2 nor s2 ≤ s1). It need not be anti-symmetric (that is, there may be members `s1`,`s2` of `S` such that s1 ≤ s2 and s2 ≤ s1 but `s1` and `s2` are not identical). Some examples: * sentences ordered by logical implication ("p and p" implies and is implied by "p", but these sentences are not identical; so this illustrates a pre-order without anti-symmetry) * sets ordered by size (this illustrates it too) - Any pre-order (S,≤) generates a category whose elements are the members of `S` and which has only a single morphism between any two elements `s1` and `s2`, iff s1≤s2. + Any pre-order (S,≤) generates a category whose elements are the members of `S` and which has only a single morphism between any two elements `s1` and `s2`, iff s1 ≤ s2. Functors @@ -122,10 +124,10 @@ Consider four categories B, C, D, and E. Let `F` be - B -+ +--- C --+ +---- D -----+ +-- E -- | | | | | | F: ------> G: ------> K: ------> - | | | | | η | | | ψ + | | | | | η | | | ψ | | | | v | | v | | H: ------> L: ------> - | | | | | φ | | + | | | | | φ | | | | | | v | | | | J: ------> | | -----+ +--------+ +------------+ +------- @@ -136,7 +138,7 @@ Then (η F) is a natural transformation from the (composite) fun And (K η) is a natural transformation from the (composite) functor `KG` to the (composite) functor `KH`, such that where `C1` is an element of category C, (K η)[C1] = K(η[C1])---that is, the morphism in E that `K` assigns to the morphism η[C1] of D. -(φ -v- η) is a natural transformation from `G` to `J`; this is known as a "vertical composition". We will rely later on this, where f:C1→C2: +(φ -v- η) is a natural transformation from `G` to `J`; this is known as a "vertical composition". For any morphism f:C1→C2 in C:
 	φ[C2] ∘ H(f) ∘ η[C1] = φ[C2] ∘ H(f) ∘ η[C1]
@@ -154,7 +156,7 @@ by naturalness of η, is:
 	φ[C2] ∘ η[C2] ∘ G(f) = J(f) ∘ φ[C1] ∘ η[C1]
 
-Hence, we can define (φ -v- η)[x] as: φ[x] ∘ η[x] and rely on it to satisfy the constraints for a natural transformation from `G` to `J`: +Hence, we can define (φ -v- η)[\_] as: φ[\_] ∘ η[\_] and rely on it to satisfy the constraints for a natural transformation from `G` to `J`:
 	(φ -v- η)[C2] ∘ G(f) = J(f) ∘ (φ -v- η)[C1]
@@ -173,7 +175,7 @@ I'll assert without proving that vertical composition is associative and has an
 
 
 	(φ -h- η)[C1]  =  L(η[C1]) ∘ ψ[G(C1)]
-					   =  ψ[H(C1)] ∘ K(η[C1])
+				   =  ψ[H(C1)] ∘ K(η[C1])
 
Horizontal composition is also associative, and has the same identity as vertical composition. @@ -186,234 +188,423 @@ In earlier days, these were also called "triples." A **monad** is a structure consisting of an (endo)functor `M` from some category C to itself, along with some natural transformations, which we'll specify in a moment. -Let `T` be a set of natural transformations `p`, each being between some (variable) functor `P` and another functor which is the composite `MP'` of `M` and a (variable) functor `P'`. That is, for each element `C1` in C, `p` assigns `C1` a morphism from element `P(C1)` to element `MP'(C1)`, satisfying the constraints detailed in the previous section. For different members of `T`, the relevant functors may differ; that is, `p` is a transformation from functor `P` to `MP'`, `q` is a transformation from functor `Q` to `MQ'`, and none of `P`, `P'`, `Q`, `Q'` need be the same. +Let `T` be a set of natural transformations φ, each being between some arbitrary endofunctor `F` on C and another functor which is the composite `MF'` of `M` and another arbitrary endofunctor `F'` on C. That is, for each element `C1` in C, φ assigns `C1` a morphism from element `F(C1)` to element `MF'(C1)`, satisfying the constraints detailed in the previous section. For different members of `T`, the relevant functors may differ; that is, φ is a transformation from functor `F` to `MF'`, γ is a transformation from functor `G` to `MG'`, and none of `F`, `F'`, `G`, `G'` need be the same. -One of the members of `T` will be designated the "unit" transformation for `M`, and it will be a transformation from the identity functor `1C` for C to `M(1C)`. So it will assign to `C1` a morphism from `C1` to `M(C1)`. +One of the members of `T` will be designated the `unit` transformation for `M`, and it will be a transformation from the identity functor `1C` for C to `M(1C)`. So it will assign to `C1` a morphism from `C1` to `M(C1)`. -We also need to designate for `M` a "join" transformation, which is a natural transformation from the (composite) functor `MM` to `M`. +We also need to designate for `M` a `join` transformation, which is a natural transformation from the (composite) functor `MM` to `M`. These two natural transformations have to satisfy some constraints ("the monad laws") which are most easily stated if we can introduce a defined notion. -Let `p` and `q` be members of `T`, that is they are natural transformations from `P` to `MP'` and from `Q` to `MQ'`, respectively. Let them be such that `P' = Q`. Now `(M q)` will also be a natural transformation, formed by composing the functor `M` with the natural transformation `q`. Similarly, `(join Q')` will be a natural transformation, formed by composing the natural transformation `join` with the functor `Q'`; it will transform the functor `MMQ'` to the functor `MQ'`. Now take the vertical composition of the three natural transformations `(join Q')`, `(M q)`, and `p`, and abbreviate it as follows: - - q <=< p =def. ((join Q') -v- (M q) -v- p) +Let φ and γ be members of `T`, that is they are natural transformations from `F` to `MF'` and from `G` to `MG'`, respectively. Let them be such that `F' = G`. Now (M γ) will also be a natural transformation, formed by composing the functor `M` with the natural transformation γ. Similarly, `(join G')` will be a natural transformation, formed by composing the natural transformation `join` with the functor `G'`; it will transform the functor `MMG'` to the functor `MG'`. Now take the vertical composition of the three natural transformations `(join G')`, (M γ), and φ, and abbreviate it as follows. Since composition is associative I don't specify the order of composition on the rhs. -Since composition is associative I don't specify the order of composition on the rhs. +
+	γ <=< φ  =def.  ((join G') -v- (M γ) -v- φ)
+
-In other words, `<=<` is a binary operator that takes us from two members `p` and `q` of `T` to a composite natural transformation. (In functional programming, at least, this is called the "Kleisli composition operator". Sometimes its written `p >=> q` where that's the same as `q <=< p`.) +In other words, `<=<` is a binary operator that takes us from two members φ and γ of `T` to a composite natural transformation. (In functional programming, at least, this is called the "Kleisli composition operator". Sometimes it's written φ >=> γ where that's the same as γ <=< φ.) -`p` is a transformation from `P` to `MP'` which = `MQ`; `(M q)` is a transformation from `MQ` to `MMQ'`; and `(join Q')` is a transformation from `MMQ'` to `MQ'`. So the composite `q <=< p` will be a transformation from `P` to `MQ'`, and so also eligible to be a member of `T`. +φ is a transformation from `F` to `MF'`, where the latter = `MG`; (M γ) is a transformation from `MG` to `MMG'`; and `(join G')` is a transformation from `MMG'` to `MG'`. So the composite γ <=< φ will be a transformation from `F` to `MG'`, and so also eligible to be a member of `T`. Now we can specify the "monad laws" governing a monad as follows: +
	
 	(T, <=<, unit) constitute a monoid
+
+ +That's it. Well, there may be a wrinkle here. I don't know whether the definition of a monoid requires the operation to be defined for every pair in its set. In the present case, γ <=< φ isn't fully defined on `T`, but only when φ is a transformation to some `MF'` and γ is a transformation from `F'`. But wherever `<=<` is defined, the monoid laws must hold: + +
+	    (i) γ <=< φ is also in T
+
+	   (ii) (ρ <=< γ) <=< φ  =  ρ <=< (γ <=< φ)
+
+	(iii.1) unit <=< φ  =  φ
+	        (here φ has to be a natural transformation to M(1C))
+
+	(iii.2)                ρ  =  ρ <=< unit
+	        (here ρ has to be a natural transformation from 1C)
+
+ +If φ is a natural transformation from `F` to `M(1C)` and γ is (φ G'), that is, a natural transformation from `FG'` to `MG'`, then we can extend (iii.1) as follows: + +
+	γ = (φ G')
+	  = ((unit <=< φ) G')
+	  since unit is a natural transformation to M(1C), this is:
+	  = (((join 1C) -v- (M unit) -v- φ) G')
+	  = (((join 1C) G') -v- ((M unit) G') -v- (φ G'))
+	  = ((join (1C G')) -v- (M (unit G')) -v- γ)
+	  = ((join G') -v- (M (unit G')) -v- γ)
+	  since (unit G') is a natural transformation to MG', this is:
+	  = (unit G') <=< γ
+
-That's it. (Well, perhaps we're cheating a bit, because `q <=< p` isn't fully defined on `T`, but only when `P` is a functor to `MP'` and `Q` is a functor from `P'`. But wherever `<=<` is defined, the monoid laws are satisfied: +where as we said γ is a natural transformation from some `FG'` to `MG'`. - (i) q <=< p is also in T - (ii) (r <=< q) <=< p = r <=< (q <=< p) - (iii.1) unit <=< p = p (here p has to be a natural transformation to M(1C)) - (iii.2) p = p <=< unit (here p has to be a natural transformation from 1C) +Similarly, if ρ is a natural transformation from `1C` to `MR'`, and γ is (ρ G), that is, a natural transformation from `G` to `MR'G`, then we can extend (iii.2) as follows: -If `p` is a natural transformation from `P` to `M(1C)` and `q` is `(p Q')`, that is, a natural transformation from `PQ` to `MQ`, then we can extend (iii.1) as follows: +
+	γ = (ρ G)
+	  = ((ρ <=< unit) G)
+	  = since ρ is a natural transformation to MR', this is:
+	  = (((join R') -v- (M ρ) -v- unit) G)
+	  = (((join R') G) -v- ((M ρ) G) -v- (unit G))
+	  = ((join (R'G)) -v- (M (ρ G)) -v- (unit G))
+	  since γ = (ρ G) is a natural transformation to MR'G, this is:
+	  = γ <=< (unit G)
+
- q = (p Q') - = ((unit <=< p) Q') - = ((join -v- (M unit) -v- p) Q') - = (join Q') -v- ((M unit) Q') -v- (p Q') - = (join Q') -v- (M (unit Q')) -v- q - ?? - = (unit Q') <=< q +where as we said γ is a natural transformation from `G` to some `MR'G`. -where as we said `q` is a natural transformation from some `PQ'` to `MQ'`. +Summarizing then, the monad laws can be expressed as: -Similarly, if `p` is a natural transformation from `1C` to `MP'`, and `q` is `(p Q)`, that is, a natural transformation from `Q` to `MP'Q`, then we can extend (iii.2) as follows: +
+	For all ρ, γ, φ in T for which ρ <=< γ and γ <=< φ are defined:
+
+	    (i) γ <=< φ etc are also in T
 
-	q = (p Q)
-	  = ((p <=< unit) Q)
-	  = (((join P') -v- (M p) -v- unit) Q)
-	  = ((join P'Q) -v- ((M p) Q) -v- (unit Q))
-	  = ((join P'Q) -v- (M (p Q)) -v- (unit Q))
-	  ??
-	  = q <=< (unit Q)
+	   (ii) (ρ <=< γ) <=< φ  =  ρ <=< (γ <=< φ)
 
-where as we said `q` is a natural transformation from `Q` to some `MP'Q`.
+	(iii.1) (unit G') <=< γ  =  γ
+	        whenever γ is a natural transformation from some FG' to MG'
 
+	(iii.2)                     γ  =  γ <=< (unit G)
+	        whenever γ is a natural transformation from G to some MR'G
+
-The standard category-theory presentation of the monad laws ------------------------------------------------------------ +Getting to the standard category-theory presentation of the monad laws +---------------------------------------------------------------------- In category theory, the monad laws are usually stated in terms of `unit` and `join` instead of `unit` and `<=<`. -(* + -Let's remind ourselves of some principles: - * composition of morphisms, functors, and natural compositions is associative - * functors "distribute over composition", that is for any morphisms f and g in F's source category: F(g ∘ f) = F(g) ∘ F(f) - * if η is a natural transformation from F to G, then for every f:C1→C2 in F and G's source category C: η[C2] ∘ F(f) = G(f) ∘ η[C1]. +Let's remind ourselves of principles stated above: +* composition of morphisms, functors, and natural compositions is associative + +* functors "distribute over composition", that is for any morphisms `f` and `g` in `F`'s source category: F(g ∘ f) = F(g) ∘ F(f) + +* if η is a natural transformation from `G` to `H`, then for every f:C1→C2 in `G` and `H`'s source category C: η[C2] ∘ G(f) = H(f) ∘ η[C1]. + +* (η F)[X] = η[F(X)] + +* (K η)[X] = K(η[X]) + +* ((φ -v- η) F) = ((φ F) -v- (η F)) Let's use the definitions of naturalness, and of composition of natural transformations, to establish two lemmas. -Recall that join is a natural transformation from the (composite) functor MM to M. So for elements C1 in C, join[C1] will be a morphism from MM(C1) to M(C1). And for any morphism f:a→b in C: +Recall that `join` is a natural transformation from the (composite) functor `MM` to `M`. So for elements `C1` in C, `join[C1]` will be a morphism from `MM(C1)` to `M(C1)`. And for any morphism f:C1→C2 in C: + +
+	(1) join[C2] ∘ MM(f)  =  M(f) ∘ join[C1]
+
+ +Next, let γ be a transformation from `G` to `MG'`, and + consider the composite transformation ((join MG') -v- (MM γ)). - (1) join[b] ∘ MM(f) = M(f) ∘ join[a] +* γ assigns elements `C1` in C a morphism γ\*:G(C1) → MG'(C1). (MM γ) is a transformation that instead assigns `C1` the morphism MM(γ\*). -Next, consider the composite transformation ((join MQ') -v- (MM q)). - q is a transformation from Q to MQ', and assigns elements C1 in C a morphism q*: Q(C1) → MQ'(C1). (MM q) is a transformation that instead assigns C1 the morphism MM(q*). - (join MQ') is a transformation from MMMQ' to MMQ' that assigns C1 the morphism join[MQ'(C1)]. - Composing them: - (2) ((join MQ') -v- (MM q)) assigns to C1 the morphism join[MQ'(C1)] ∘ MM(q*). +* `(join MG')` is a transformation from `MM(MG')` to `M(MG')` that assigns `C1` the morphism `join[MG'(C1)]`. -Next, consider the composite transformation ((M q) -v- (join Q)). - (3) This assigns to C1 the morphism M(q*) ∘ join[Q(C1)]. +Composing them: -So for every element C1 of C: - ((join MQ') -v- (MM q))[C1], by (2) is: - join[MQ'(C1)] ∘ MM(q*), which by (1), with f=q*: Q(C1)→MQ'(C1) is: - M(q*) ∘ join[Q(C1)], which by 3 is: - ((M q) -v- (join Q))[C1] +
+	(2) ((join MG') -v- (MM γ)) assigns to C1 the morphism join[MG'(C1)] ∘ MM(γ*).
+
+ +Next, consider the composite transformation ((M γ) -v- (join G)): + +
+	(3) ((M γ) -v- (join G)) assigns to C1 the morphism M(γ*) ∘ join[G(C1)].
+
+ +So for every element `C1` of C: + +
+	((join MG') -v- (MM γ))[C1], by (2) is:
+	join[MG'(C1)] ∘ MM(γ*), which by (1), with f=γ*:G(C1)→MG'(C1) is:
+	M(γ*) ∘ join[G(C1)], which by 3 is:
+	((M γ) -v- (join G))[C1]
+
+ +So our **(lemma 1)** is: -So our (lemma 1) is: ((join MQ') -v- (MM q)) = ((M q) -v- (join Q)), where q is a transformation from Q to MQ'. +
+	((join MG') -v- (MM γ))  =  ((M γ) -v- (join G)),
+	where as we said γ is a natural transformation from G to MG'.
+
+ + +Next recall that `unit` is a natural transformation from `1C` to `M`. So for elements `C1` in C, `unit[C1]` will be a morphism from `C1` to `M(C1)`. And for any morphism f:C1→C2 in C: + +
+	(4) unit[C2] ∘ f = M(f) ∘ unit[C1]
+
+Next, consider the composite transformation ((M γ) -v- (unit G)): -Next recall that unit is a natural transformation from 1C to M. So for elements C1 in C, unit[C1] will be a morphism from C1 to M(C1). And for any morphism f:a→b in C: - (4) unit[b] ∘ f = M(f) ∘ unit[a] +
+	(5) ((M γ) -v- (unit G)) assigns to C1 the morphism M(γ*) ∘ unit[G(C1)].
+
-Next consider the composite transformation ((M q) -v- (unit Q)). (5) This assigns to C1 the morphism M(q*) ∘ unit[Q(C1)]. +Next, consider the composite transformation ((unit MG') -v- γ): -Next consider the composite transformation ((unit MQ') -v- q). (6) This assigns to C1 the morphism unit[MQ'(C1)] ∘ q*. +
+	(6) ((unit MG') -v- γ) assigns to C1 the morphism unit[MG'(C1)] ∘ γ*.
+
So for every element C1 of C: - ((M q) -v- (unit Q))[C1], by (5) = - M(q*) ∘ unit[Q(C1)], which by (4), with f=q*: Q(C1)→MQ'(C1) is: - unit[MQ'(C1)] ∘ q*, which by (6) = - ((unit MQ') -v- q)[C1] -So our lemma (2) is: (((M q) -v- (unit Q)) = ((unit MQ') -v- q)), where q is a transformation from Q to MQ'. +
+	((M γ) -v- (unit G))[C1], by (5) =
+	M(γ*) ∘ unit[G(C1)], which by (4), with f=γ*:G(C1)→MG'(C1) is:
+	unit[MG'(C1)] ∘ γ*, which by (6) =
+	((unit MG') -v- γ)[C1]
+
+So our **(lemma 2)** is: -Finally, we substitute ((join Q') -v- (M q) -v- p) for q <=< p in the monad laws. For simplicity, I'll omit the "-v-". +
+	(((M γ) -v- (unit G))  =  ((unit MG') -v- γ)),
+	where as we said γ is a natural transformation from G to MG'.
+
- for all p,q,r in T, where p is a transformation from P to MP', q is a transformation from Q to MQ', R is a transformation from R to MR', and P'=Q and Q'=R: - (i) q <=< p etc are also in T - ==> - (i') ((join Q') (M q) p) etc are also in T +Finally, we substitute ((join G') -v- (M γ) -v- φ) for γ <=< φ in the monad laws. For simplicity, I'll omit the "-v-". +
+	For all ρ, γ, φ in T,
+	where φ is a transformation from F to MF',
+	γ is a transformation from G to MG',
+	ρ is a transformation from R to MR',
+	and F'=G and G'=R:
 
-	(ii) (r <=< q) <=< p  =  r <=< (q <=< p)
+	     (i) γ <=< φ etc are also in T
 	==>
-		 (r <=< q) is a transformation from Q to MR', so:
-			(r <=< q) <=< p becomes: (join R') (M (r <=< q)) p
-							which is: (join R') (M ((join R') (M r) q)) p
-		 	substituting in (ii), and helping ourselves to associativity on the rhs, we get:
+	    (i') ((join G') (M γ) φ) etc are also in T
+
- ((join R') (M ((join R') (M r) q)) p) = ((join R') (M r) (join Q') (M q) p) - --------------------- - which by the distributivity of functors over composition, and helping ourselves to associativity on the lhs, yields: - ------------------------ - ((join R') (M join R') (MM r) (M q) p) = ((join R') (M r) (join Q') (M q) p) - --------------- - which by lemma 1, with r a transformation from Q' to MR', yields: - ----------------- - ((join R') (M join R') (MM r) (M q) p) = ((join R') (join MR') (MM r) (M q) p) +
+	    (ii) (ρ <=< γ) <=< φ  =  ρ <=< (γ <=< φ)
+	==>
+		     (ρ <=< γ) is a transformation from G to MR', so
+			 (ρ <=< γ) <=< φ becomes: ((join R') (M (ρ <=< γ)) φ)
+							which is: ((join R') (M ((join R') (M ρ) γ)) φ)
 
-			which will be true for all r,q,p just in case:
+			 similarly, ρ <=< (γ <=< φ) is:
+							((join R') (M ρ) ((join G') (M γ) φ))
 
-	      ((join R') (M join R')) = ((join R') (join MR')), for any R'.
+		 	 substituting these into (ii), and helping ourselves to associativity on the rhs, we get:
+	         ((join R') (M ((join R') (M ρ) γ)) φ) = ((join R') (M ρ) (join G') (M γ) φ)
+    
+			 which by the distributivity of functors over composition, and helping ourselves to associativity on the lhs, yields:
+	         ((join R') (M join R') (MM ρ) (M γ) φ) = ((join R') (M ρ) (join G') (M γ) φ)
+  
+			 which by lemma 1, with ρ a transformation from G' to MR', yields:
+	         ((join R') (M join R') (MM ρ) (M γ) φ) = ((join R') (join MR') (MM ρ) (M γ) φ)
 
-			which will in turn be true just in case:
+			 [-- Are the next two steps too cavalier? --]
 
-	(ii') (join (M join)) = (join (join M))
+			 which will be true for all ρ, γ, φ only when:
+	         ((join R') (M join R')) = ((join R') (join MR')), for any R'
 
+			 which will in turn be true when:
+       (ii') (join (M join)) = (join (join M))
+
- (iii.1) (unit P') <=< p = p +
+	 (iii.1) (unit G') <=< γ  =  γ
+	         when γ is a natural transformation from some FG' to MG'
 	==>
-			(unit P') is a transformation from P' to MP', so:
-				(unit P') <=< p becomes: (join P') (M unit P') p
-						   which is: (join P') (M unit P') p
-				substituting in (iii.1), we get:
-			((join P') (M unit P') p) = p
+			 (unit G') is a transformation from G' to MG', so:
+			 (unit G') <=< γ becomes: ((join G') (M (unit G')) γ)
+			                      which is: ((join G') ((M unit) G') γ)
 
-			which will be true for all p just in case:
+			 substituting in (iii.1), we get:
+			 ((join G') ((M unit) G') γ) = γ
 
-	         ((join P') (M unit P')) = the identity transformation, for any P'
+			 which is:
+			 (((join (M unit)) G') γ) = γ
 
-			which will in turn be true just in case:
+			 [-- Are the next two steps too cavalier? --]
 
-	(iii.1') (join (M unit) = the identity transformation
+			 which will be true for all γ just in case:
+			 for any G', ((join (M unit)) G') = the identity transformation
 
+			 which will in turn be true just in case:
+	(iii.1') (join (M unit)) = the identity transformation
+
- (iii.2) p = p <=< (unit P) +
+	 (iii.2) γ  =  γ <=< (unit G)
+	         when γ is a natural transformation from G to some MR'G
 	==>
-			p is a transformation from P to MP', so:
-				unit <=< p becomes: (join P') (M p) unit
-				substituting in (iii.2), we get:
-			p = ((join P') (M p) (unit P))
-						   --------------
-				which by lemma (2), yields:
-                            ------------
-			p = ((join P') ((unit MP') p)
+			 γ <=< (unit G) becomes: ((join R'G) (M γ) (unit G))
+			
+			 substituting in (iii.2), we get:
+			 γ = ((join R'G) (M γ) (unit G))
+		
+			 which by lemma 2, yields:
+			 γ = (((join R'G) ((unit MR'G) γ)
 
-				which will be true for all p just in case:
+			 which is:
+			 γ = (((join (unit M)) R'G) γ)
 
-	        ((join P') (unit MP')) = the identity transformation, for any P'
+			 [-- Are the next two steps too cavalier? --]
 
-				which will in turn be true just in case:
+			  which will be true for all γ just in case:
+			 for any R'G, ((join (unit M)) R'G) = the identity transformation
 
+			 which will in turn be true just in case:
 	(iii.2') (join (unit M)) = the identity transformation
+
Collecting the results, our monad laws turn out in this format to be: - when p a transformation from P to MP', q a transformation from P' to MQ', r a transformation from Q' to MR' all in T: +
+	For all ρ, γ, φ in T,
+	where φ is a transformation from F to MF',
+	γ is a transformation from G to MG',
+	ρ is a transformation from R to MR',
+	and F'=G and G'=R:
 
-	(i') ((join Q') (M q) p) etc also in T
+	    (i') ((join G') (M γ) φ) etc also in T
 
-	(ii') (join (M join)) = (join (join M))
+	   (ii') (join (M join)) = (join (join M))
 
 	(iii.1') (join (M unit)) = the identity transformation
 
-	(iii.2')(join (unit M)) = the identity transformation
-
+	(iii.2') (join (unit M)) = the identity transformation
+
-7. The functional programming presentation of the monad laws ------------------------------------------------------------- -In functional programming, unit is usually called "return" and the monad laws are usually stated in terms of return and an operation called "bind" which is interdefinable with <=< or with join. -Additionally, whereas in category-theory one works "monomorphically", in functional programming one usually works with "polymorphic" functions. +Getting to the functional programming presentation of the monad laws +-------------------------------------------------------------------- +In functional programming, `unit` is sometimes called `return` and the monad laws are usually stated in terms of `unit`/`return` and an operation called `bind` which is interdefinable with `<=<` or with `join`. The base category C will have types as elements, and monadic functions as its morphisms. The source and target of a morphism will be the types of its argument and its result. (As always, there can be multiple distinct morphisms from the same source to the same target.) -A monad M will consist of a mapping from types C1 to types M(C1), and a mapping from functions f:C1→C2 to functions M(f):M(C1)→M(C2). This is also known as "fmap f" or "liftM f" for M, and is called "function f lifted into the monad M." For example, where M is the list monad, M maps every type X into the type "list of Xs", and maps every function f:x→y into the function that maps [x1,x2...] to [y1,y2,...]. +A monad `M` will consist of a mapping from types `'t` to types `M('t)`, and a mapping from functions f:C1→C2 to functions M(f):M(C1)→M(C2). This is also known as liftM f for `M`, and is pronounced "function f lifted into the monad M." For example, where `M` is the list monad, `M` maps every type `'t` into the type `'t list`, and maps every function f:x→y into the function that maps `[x1,x2...]` to `[y1,y2,...]`. + + +In functional programming, instead of working with natural transformations we work with "monadic values" and polymorphic functions "into the monad." + +A "monadic value" is any member of a type `M('t)`, for any type `'t`. For example, any `int list` is a monadic value for the list monad. We can think of these monadic values as the result of applying some function `phi`, whose type is `F('t)->M(F'('t))`. `'t` here is any collection of free type variables, and `F('t)` and `F'('t)` are types parameterized on `'t`. An example, with `M` being the list monad, `'t` being `('t1,'t2)`, `F('t1,'t2)` being `char * 't1 * 't2`, and `F'('t1,'t2)` being `int * 't1 * 't2`: + +
+	let phi = fun ((_:char, x y) -> [(1,x,y),(2,x,y)]
+
+ + + +Now where `gamma` is another function of type F'('t) → M(G'('t)), we define: + +
+	gamma =<< phi a  =def. ((join G') -v- (M gamma)) (phi a)
+	                 = ((join G') -v- (M gamma) -v- phi) a
+					 = (gamma <=< phi) a
+
+ +Hence: + +
+	gamma <=< phi = fun a -> (gamma =<< phi a)
+
+ +`gamma =<< phi a` is called the operation of "binding" the function gamma to the monadic value `phi a`, and is usually written as `phi a >>= gamma`. + +With these definitions, our monadic laws become: + + +
+	Where phi is a polymorphic function of type F('t) -> M(F'('t))
+	gamma is a polymorphic function of type G('t) -> M(G'('t))
+	rho is a polymorphic function of type R('t) -> M(R'('t))
+	and F' = G and G' = R, 
+	and a ranges over values of type F('t),
+	b ranges over values of type G('t),
+	and c ranges over values of type G'('t):
+
+	      (i) γ <=< φ is defined,
+			  and is a natural transformation from F to MG'
+	==>
+		(i'') fun a -> gamma =<< phi a is defined,
+			  and is a function from type F('t) -> M(G'('t))
+
+ +
+	     (ii) (ρ <=< γ) <=< φ  =  ρ <=< (γ <=< φ)
+	==>
+			  (fun a -> (rho <=< gamma) =<< phi a)  =  (fun a -> rho =<< (gamma <=< phi) a)
+			  (fun a -> (fun b -> rho =<< gamma b) =<< phi a)  =  (fun a -> rho =<< (gamma =<< phi a))
+
+	   (ii'') (fun b -> rho =<< gamma b) =<< phi a  =  rho =<< (gamma =<< phi a)
+
+ +
+	  (iii.1) (unit G') <=< γ  =  γ
+	          when γ is a natural transformation from some FG' to MG'
+	==>
+			  (unit G') <=< gamma  =  gamma
+			  when gamma is a function of type F(G'('t)) -> M(G'('t))
+
+			  fun b -> (unit G') =<< gamma b  =  gamma
+
+			  (unit G') =<< gamma b  =  gamma b
 
+			  Let return be a polymorphic function mapping arguments of any
+			  type 't to M('t). In particular, it maps arguments c of type
+			  G'('t) to the monadic value (unit G') c, of type M(G'('t)).
 
+	(iii.1'') return =<< gamma b  =  gamma b
+
+ +
+	  (iii.2) γ  =  γ <=< (unit G)
+	          when γ is a natural transformation from G to some MR'G
+	==>
+			  gamma  =  gamma <=< (unit G)
+			  when gamma is a function of type G('t) -> M(R'(G('t)))
 
+			  gamma  =  fun b -> gamma =<< (unit G) b
 
-A natural transformation t assigns to each type C1 in C a morphism t[C1]: C1→M(C1) such that, for every f:C1→C2:
-	t[C2] ∘ f = M(f) ∘ t[C1]
+			  As above, return will map arguments b of type G('t) to the
+			  monadic value (unit G) b, of type M(G('t)).
+
+			  gamma  =  fun b -> gamma =<< return b
+
+	(iii.2'') gamma b  =  gamma =<< return b
+
-The composite morphisms said here to be identical are morphisms from the type C1 to the type M(C2). +Summarizing (ii''), (iii.1''), (iii.2''), these are the monadic laws as usually stated in the functional programming literature: +* `fun b -> rho =<< gamma b) =<< phi a = rho =<< (gamma =<< phi a)` + Usually written reversed, and with a monadic variable `u` standing in + for `phi a`: -In functional programming, instead of working with natural transformations we work with "monadic values" and polymorphic functions "into the monad" in question. + `u >>= (fun b -> gamma b >>= rho) = (u >>= gamma) >>= rho` -For an example of the latter, let p be a function that takes arguments of some (schematic, polymorphic) type C1 and yields results of some (schematic, polymorphic) type M(C2). An example with M being the list monad, and C2 being the tuple type schema int * C1: +* `return =<< gamma b = gamma b` - let p = fun c → [(1,c), (2,c)] + Usually written reversed, and with `u` standing in for `gamma b`: -p is polymorphic: when you apply it to the int 0 you get a result of type "list of int * int": [(1,0), (2,0)]. When you apply it to the char 'e' you get a result of type "list of int * char": [(1,'e'), (2,'e')]. + `u >>= return = u` -However, to keep things simple, we'll work instead with functions whose type is settled. So instead of the polymorphic p, we'll work with (p : C1 → M(int * C1)). This only accepts arguments of type C1. For generality, I'll talk of functions with the type (p : C1 → M(C1')), where we assume that C1' is a function of C1. +* `gamma b = gamma =<< return b` -A "monadic value" is any member of a type M(C1), for any type C1. For example, a list is a monadic value for the list monad. We can think of these monadic values as the result of applying some function (p : C1 → M(C1')) to an argument of type C1. + Usually written reversed: + `return b >>= gamma = gamma b` +