Today we're going to encounter continuations. We're going to come at them from three different directions, and each time we're going to end up at the same place: a particular monad, which we'll call the continuation monad. The three approches are: [[!toc]] Rethinking the list monad ------------------------- To construct a monad, the key element is to settle on a type constructor, and the monad naturally follows from that. I'll remind you of some examples of how monads follow from the type constructor in a moment. This will involve some review of familair material, but it's worth doing for two reasons: it will set up a pattern for the new discussion further below, and it will tie together some previously unconnected elements of the course (more specifically, version 3 lists and monads). For instance, take the **Reader Monad**. Once we decide that the type constructor is type 'a reader = fun e:env -> 'a then we can deduce the unit and the bind: r_unit x:'a -> 'a reader = fun (e:env) -> x Since the type of an `'a reader` is `fun e:env -> 'a` (by definition), the type of the `r_unit` function is `'a -> e:env -> 'a`, which is a specific case of the type of the *K* combinator. So it makes sense that *K* is the unit for the reader monad. Since the type of the `bind` operator is required to be r_bind:('a reader) -> ('a -> 'b reader) -> ('b reader) We can deduce the correct `bind` function as follows: r_bind (u:'a reader) (f:'a -> 'b reader):('b reader) = We have to open up the `u` box and get out the `'a` object in order to feed it to `f`. Since `u` is a function from environments to objects of type `'a`, the way we open a box in this monad is by applying it to an environment: .... f (u e) ... This subexpression types to `'b reader`, which is good. The only problem is that we invented an environment `e` that we didn't already have , so we have to abstract over that variable to balance the books: fun e -> f (u e) ... This types to `env -> 'b reader`, but we want to end up with `env -> 'b`. Once again, the easiest way to turn a `'b reader` into a `'b` is to apply it to an environment. So we end up as follows: r_bind (u:'a reader) (f:'a -> 'b reader):('b reader) = f (u e) e And we're done. The **State Monad** is similar. We somehow intuit that we want to use the following type constructor: type 'a state = 'store -> ('a, 'store) So our unit is naturally let s_unit (x:'a):('a state) = fun (s:'store) -> (x, s) And we deduce the bind in a way similar to the reasoning given above. First, we need to apply `f` to the contents of the `u` box: let s_bind (u:'a state) (f:'a -> ('b state)):('b state) = But unlocking the `u` box is a little more complicated. As before, we need to posit a state `s` that we can apply `u` to. Once we do so, however, we won't have an `'a`, we'll have a pair whose first element is an `'a`. So we have to unpack the pair: ... let (a, s') = u s in ... (f a) ... Abstracting over the `s` and adjusting the types gives the result: let s_bind (u:'a state) (f:'a -> ('b state)):('b state) = fun (s:state) -> let (a, s') = u s in f a s' The **Option Monad** doesn't follow the same pattern so closely, so we won't pause to explore it here, though conceptually its unit and bind follow just as naturally from its type constructor. Our other familiar monad is the **List Monad**, which we were told looks like this: type 'a list = ['a];; l_unit (x:'a) = [x];; l_bind u f = List.concat (List.map f u);; Recall that `List.map` take a function and a list and returns the result to applying the function to the elements of the list: List.map (fun i -> [i;i+1]) [1;2] ~~> [[1; 2]; [2; 3]] and List.concat takes a list of lists and erases the embdded list boundaries: List.concat [[1; 2]; [2; 3]] ~~> [1; 2; 2; 3] And sure enough, l_bind [1;2] (fun i -> [i, i+1]) ~~> [1; 2; 2; 3] But where is the reasoning that led us to this unit and bind? And what is the type `['a]`? Magic. So let's take a *completely useless digressing* and see if we can gain some insight into the details of the List monad. Let's choose type constructor that we can peer into, using some of the technology we built up so laboriously during the first half of the course. I'm going to use type 3 lists, partly because I know they'll give the result I want, but also because they're my favorite. These were the lists that made lists look like Church numerals with extra bits embdded in them: empty list: fun f z -> z list with one element: fun f z -> f 1 z list with two elements: fun f z -> f 2 (f 1 z) list with three elements: fun f z -> f 3 (f 2 (f 1 z)) and so on. To save time, we'll let the Ocaml interpreter infer the principle types of these functions (rather than deducing what the types should be):
# fun f z -> z;;
- : 'a -> 'b -> 'b = 
# fun f z -> f 1 z;;
- : (int -> 'a -> 'b) -> 'a -> 'b = 
# fun f z -> f 2 (f 1 z);;
- : (int -> 'a -> 'a) -> 'a -> 'a = 
# fun f z -> f 3 (f 2 (f 1 z))
- : (int -> 'a -> 'a) -> 'a -> 'a = 
Finally, we're getting consistent principle types, so we can stop. These types should remind you of the simply-typed lambda calculus types for Church numerals (`(o -> o) -> o -> o`) with one extra bit thrown in (in this case, and int). So here's our type constructor for our hand-rolled lists: type 'a list' = (int -> 'a -> 'a) -> 'a -> 'a Generalizing to lists that contain any kind of element (not just ints), we have type ('a, 'b) list' = ('a -> 'b -> 'b) -> 'b -> 'b So an `('a, 'b) list'` is a list containing elements of type `'a`, where `'b` is the type of some part of the plumbing. This is more general than an ordinary Ocaml list, but we'll see how to map them into Ocaml lists soon. We don't need to grasp the role of the `'b`'s in order to proceed to build a monad: l'_unit (x:'a):(('a, 'b) list) = fun x -> fun f z -> f x z No problem. Arriving at bind is a little more complicated, but exactly the same principles apply, you just have to be careful and systematic about it. l'_bind (u:('a,'b) list') (f:'a -> ('c, 'd) list'): ('c, 'd) list' = ... Unfortunately, we'll need to spell out the types: l'_bind (u: ('a -> 'b -> 'b) -> 'b -> 'b) (f: 'a -> ('c -> 'd -> 'd) -> 'd -> 'd) : ('c -> 'd -> 'd) -> 'd -> 'd = ... It's a rookie mistake to quail before complicated types. You should be no more intimiated by complex types than by a linguistic tree with deeply embedded branches: complex structure created by repeated application of simple rules. As usual, we need to unpack the `u` box. Examine the type of `u`. This time, `u` will only deliver up its contents if we give `u` as an argument a function expecting an `'a`. Once that argument is applied to an object of type `'a`, we'll have what we need. Thus: .... u (fun (x:'a) -> ... (f a) ... ) ... In order for `u` to have the kind of argument it needs, we have to adjust `(f a)` (which has type `('c -> 'd -> 'd) -> 'd -> 'd`) in order to deliver something of type `'b -> 'b`. The easiest way is to alias `'d` to `'b`, and provide `(f a)` with an argument of type `'c -> 'b -> 'b`. Thus: l'_bind (u: ('a -> 'b -> 'b) -> 'b -> 'b) (f: 'a -> ('c -> 'b -> 'b) -> 'b -> 'b) : ('c -> 'b -> 'b) -> 'b -> 'b = .... u (fun (x:'a) -> f a k) ... [Excercise: can you arrive at a fully general bind for this type constructor, one that does not collapse `'d`'s with `'b`'s?] As usual, we have to abstract over `k`, but this time, no further adjustments are needed: l'_bind (u: ('a -> 'b -> 'b) -> 'b -> 'b) (f: 'a -> ('c -> 'b -> 'b) -> 'b -> 'b) : ('c -> 'b -> 'b) -> 'b -> 'b = fun (k:'c -> 'b -> 'b) -> u (fun (x:'a) -> f a k) You should carefully check to make sure that this term is consistent with the typing. Our theory is that this monad should be capable of exactly replicating the behavior of the standard List monad. Let's test: l_bind [1;2] (fun i -> [i, i+1]) ~~> [1; 2; 2; 3] l'_bind (fun f z -> f 1 (f 2 z)) (fun i -> fun f z -> f i (f (i+1) z)) ~~> Sigh. Ocaml won't show us our own list. So we have to choose an `f` and a `z` that will turn our hand-crafted lists into standard Ocaml lists, so that they will print out.
# let cons h t = h :: t;;  (* Ocaml is stupid about :: *)
# l'_bind (fun f z -> f 1 (f 2 z)) 
          (fun i -> fun f z -> f i (f (i+1) z)) cons [];;
- : int list = [1; 2; 2; 3]
Ta da! Just for mnemonic purposes (sneaking in an instance of eta reduction to the definition of unit), we can summarize the result as follows: type ('a, 'b) list' = ('a -> 'b -> 'b) -> 'b -> 'b l'_unit x = fun f -> f x l'_bind u f = fun k -> u (fun x -> f x k) To bad this digression, though it ties together various elements of the course, has *no relevance whatsoever* to the topic of continuations. Montague's PTQ treatment of DPs as generalized quantifiers ---------------------------------------------------------- We've hinted that Montague's treatment of DPs as generalized quantifiers embodies the spirit of continuations (see de Groote 2001, Barker 2002 for lengthy discussion). Let's see why. First, we'll need a type constructor. As you probably know, Montague replaced individual-denoting determiner phrases (with type `e`) with generalized quantifiers (with [extensional] type `(e -> t) -> t`. In particular, the denotation of a proper name like *John*, which might originally denote a object `j` of type `e`, came to denote a generalized quantifier `fun pred -> pred j` of type `(e -> t) -> t`. Let's write a general function that will map individuals into their corresponding generalized quantifier: gqize (x:e) = fun (p:e->t) -> p x This function wraps up an individual in a fancy box. That is to say, we are in the presence of a monad. The type constructor, the unit and the bind follow naturally. We've done this enough times that I won't belabor the construction of the bind function, the derivation is similar to the List monad just given: type 'a continuation = ('a -> 'b) -> 'b c_unit (x:'a) = fun (p:'a -> 'b) -> p x c_bind (u:('a -> 'b) -> 'b) (f: 'a -> ('c -> 'd) -> 'd): ('c -> 'd) -> 'd = fun (k:'a -> 'b) -> u (fun (x:'a) -> f x k) How similar is it to the List monad? Let's examine the type constructor and the terms from the list monad derived above: type ('a, 'b) list' = ('a -> 'b -> 'b) -> 'b -> 'b l'_unit x = fun f -> f x l'_bind u f = fun k -> u (fun x -> f x k) (I performed a sneaky but valid eta reduction in the unit term.) The unit and the bind for the Montague continuation monad and the homemade List monad are the same terms! In other words, the behavior of the List monad and the behavior of the continuations monad are parallel in a deep sense. To emphasize the parallel, we can instantiate the type of the list' monad using the Ocaml list type: type 'a c_list = ('a -> 'a list) -> 'a list let c_list_unit x = fun f -> f x;; let c_list_bind u f = fun k -> u (fun x -> f x k);; Have we really discovered that lists are secretly continuations? Or have we merely found a way of simulating lists using list continuations? Both perspectives are valid, and we can use our intuitions about the list monad to understand continuations, and vice versa. The connections will be expecially relevant when we consider indefinites and Hamblin semantics on the linguistic side, and non-determinism on the list monad side. Refunctionalizing zippers -------------------------